Failure to define the necessary market regulation deprived lecture of the necessary nuance
The
lecture by economics Nobel laureate Joseph Stiglitz about the failures
resulting from deregulation of financial markets in the United States
and the need for a strict regulatory regime was engaging and frustrating
at the same time.
The major
weakness of the lecture was its inability to define regulation and
thereby demonstrate the complexity of the subject. So he presented
regulation as if it was a black box. Any meaningful debate about
regulation has to begin by opening the black box so that we see its
contents. This is because the arguments for and against regulation in
America often don’t illuminate the salient issues. Instead ideologues on
either side just shout at each other. This has made the debate stale.
First of
all, except for some extremist fringe, even the most ideological zealots
of deregulation are not suggesting that the USA does away with the
Securities and Exchange Commission, the Federal Reserve and many other
regulatory agencies.Government regulation of the market is a given.
Therefore, Stiglitz needed to clearly define the specific forms of
deregulation that he felt were socially harmful. Second, the issue
cannot even be how much or how less to regulate. That is a blind debate.
The debate has to be on the type of regulation sought.
The
deregulation movement of the 1980s and 90s was not born of out of the
blue. From 1954, Western nations put in place myriad regulatory policies
and institutions. This led to the growth of bloated bureaucracies with
accompanying rental havens for government officials. It also
emasculated the free operation of market forces, stifled innovation,
undermined competition, killed creativity and facilitated the growth
and dominance of monopolies and oligopolies. This in turn led to
sluggish growth and rampant inflation in the 1970s.
The
attempt to resolve these distortions came with its ideological
justification. The neo-liberal movement (as it came to be called) sought
to justify reforms through an ideological attack on government. Its
most fervent advocates sought to discredit all forms of state
involvement in the economy. The swing was therefore from one extreme
spectrum of the ideological debate to another: from an obsessive faith
is state action to a fanatical faith in the invisible hand of the
market.
I had
hoped that Stiglitz would transcend this ideological straight jacket and
therefore tell us the specific forms of regulation that hinder private
enterprise growth and stifle innovation. These regulations needed to
be removed. Then I thought he would tell us the specific regulations
that tend to protect society against the recklessness of private
economic agents without undermining innovation and creativity. Even
here I expected him to temper his argument with a caveat: that the fact
that markets fail does not necessarily mean that state intervention
would automatically produce better results.
The
lecture was therefore too narrowly focused and ideological to illuminate
the challenge we face. For example, Stiglitz recommended state
intervention in the economy, something all states do. The issue is not
whether or not to get states involved. It is not even how much or how
less they should be involved. The issue is what specific forms of
involvement are necessary for success. Yet even here, we cannot have a
one blue print for all nations.
States are
not generic. They vary in terms of their institutional capabilities
and in their politics (by politics I mean how the different constituent
social forces relate to the state). Some states are better than others
at performing particular functions. There are many state functions
that work well in Norway but would become dysfunctional if transplanted
to the US because of the differences in their institutions, politics,
cultures and other social endowments. Hence, one size cannot fit all.
Thus, I
was constantly frustrated that most ofStiglitz’s lecture was devoted to
showing how free markets do not always work as their advocates claim.
Of course I agreed with him that the argument for free markets assumes
perfect competition among firms, perfect mobility of factors of
production, perfect information among consumers etc. These assumptions
do not exist in real life because of imperfect competition, structural
barriers to entry and exit of firms into an industry and information
asymmetries.
The
problem is that Stiglitz fell into the temptation of imagining that
because free markets have an inherent tendency to simulate certain
pathologies, then state intervention to correct market failures would
work – as a matter of course. I felt like standing up to give a counter
lecture – with a zillion examples – of how state intervention to
correct market failures has often ended up creating its own
dysfunctions. Sometimes the social consequences are worse than those of
free markets.
To bring
this argument to Uganda, the free market has failed to deliver many
public goods and has actually often had harmful social effects. However,
the state we have in this country, with its institutionalised
incompetence, corruption and other dysfunctions would not be the perfect
instrument to correct many failures I see in the market. Even then,
there are particular public functions that the state in Uganda performs
well (like resource allocation through the budget) and functions (like
delivery of public goods and services to ordinary citizens) which it
performs badly.
Therefore,
the solution for Uganda, for example, would be how to leverage its
strength (allocative efficiency) while avoiding its weaknesses in
implementation of government programs. This would lead us to separate
the provision of public services from their financing. The government
would remain involved in the economy by financing education, health,
agricultural extension services, roads and energy. However, as far as
possible it should concession out the delivery of these services to the
market.The issue is not one of state versus market but how to use both
within our specific context.
No comments:
Post a Comment